Jump to content

Pseudoskepticism: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
NJGW (talk | contribs)
vast majority of sources are Truzzi
→‎Contemporary usage: trim this a bit - we already footnote the article, no need to quote vast chunks of this not particularly strong source
(2 intermediate revisions by the same user not shown)
Line 3: Line 3:
[[Image:zetetic-scholar-12-13.jpg|right|right|256px|thumb|[[Marcello Truzzi]] founded the [[Zetetic Scholar]] journal, in which he popularised the term '''''pseudoskepticism''''' in the late 1980s]]
[[Image:zetetic-scholar-12-13.jpg|right|right|256px|thumb|[[Marcello Truzzi]] founded the [[Zetetic Scholar]] journal, in which he popularised the term '''''pseudoskepticism''''' in the late 1980s]]


The term '''pseudoskepticism''' (or ''[[American and British English spelling differences|pseudoscepticism]]'') denotes thinking that appears to be skeptical but is not. The term is most commonly encountered in the form popularised by [[Marcello Truzzi]], where he defined pseudoskeptics as those who take "the negative rather than an [[agnostic]] position but still call themselves 'skeptics'".<ref>"Marcello Truzzi, [http://www.anomalist.com/commentaries/pseudo.html On Pseudo-Skepticism]" ''Zetetic Scholar'' (1987) No. 12/13, 3-4.</ref>
The term '''pseudoskepticism''' (or ''[[American and British English spelling differences|pseudoscepticism]]'') denotes thinking that appears to be skeptical but is not. The term is most commonly encountered in the form popularised by [[Marcello Truzzi]], where he defined pseudoskeptics as those who take "the negative rather than an [[agnostic]] position but still call themselves 'skeptics'".<ref name="truzzi1"/>


== Truzzi's characterisation of pseudoskeptics ==
== Truzzi's characterisation of pseudoskeptics ==


The term ''pseudoskepticism'' was popularised and characterised by Truzzi, in response to the [[skeptic groups]] who applied the label of "[[pseudoscientist]]s" to fields which Truzzi preferred to describe as [[protoscience]].<ref>Truzzi, ''ibid'', "A characteristic of many scoffers is their pejorative characterization of proponents as 'promoters' and sometimes even the most protoscientific anomaly claimants are labelled as "pseudoscientists" or practitioners of '[[pathological science]].' "</ref>
The term ''pseudoskepticism'' was popularised and characterised by Truzzi, in response to the [[skeptic groups]] who applied the label of "[[pseudoscientist]]s" to fields which Truzzi preferred to describe as [[protoscience]].<ref name="truzzi1"/>


While a Professor of Sociology at [[Eastern Michigan University]] in 1987, Truzzi gave the following description of pseudoskeptics in the journal Zetetic Scholar which he founded:
While a Professor of Sociology at [[Eastern Michigan University]] in 1987, Truzzi gave the following description of pseudoskeptics in the journal Zetetic Scholar which he founded:


{{quote|Over the years, I have decried the misuse of the term "skeptic" when used to refer to all critics of anomaly claims. Alas, the label has been thus misapplied by both proponents and critics of the paranormal. Sometimes users of the term have distinguished between so-called "soft" versus "hard" skeptics, and I in part revived the term "zetetic" because of the term's misuse. But I now think the problems created go beyond mere terminology and matters need to be set right. Since "skepticism" properly refers to doubt rather than denial--nonbelief rather than belief--critics who take the negative rather than an agnostic position but still call themselves "skeptics" are actually ''pseudo-skeptics'' and have, I believed, gained a false advantage by usurping that label." <ref>''Zetetic Scholar'' (1987) No. 12/13, 3-4.</ref>}}
{{quote|Over the years, I have decried the misuse of the term "skeptic" when used to refer to all critics of anomaly claims. Alas, the label has been thus misapplied by both proponents and critics of the paranormal. Sometimes users of the term have distinguished between so-called "soft" versus "hard" skeptics, and I in part revived the term "zetetic" because of the term's misuse. But I now think the problems created go beyond mere terminology and matters need to be set right. Since "skepticism" properly refers to doubt rather than denial--nonbelief rather than belief--critics who take the negative rather than an agnostic position but still call themselves "skeptics" are actually ''pseudo-skeptics'' and have, I believed, gained a false advantage by usurping that label."<ref name="truzzi1"/>}}

Truzzi attributed the following characteristics to pseudoskeptics:<ref name="truzzi1">{{cite journal | last = Truzzi | first = Marcello | authorlink= Marcello Truzzi | url = http://www.anomalist.com/commentaries/pseudo.html | title = On Pseudo-Skepticism | year = 1987 | journal = Zetetic Scholar | issue = 12/13 | pages = 3-4| accessdate = 2008-10-10}}</ref>


Truzzi attributed the following characteristics to pseudoskeptics:
<table><tr valign=top><td width=50%>
<table><tr valign=top><td width=50%>
*The tendency to deny, rather than doubt
*The tendency to deny, rather than doubt <ref>"Marcello Truzzi, [http://www.anomalist.com/commentaries/pseudo.html On Pseudo-Skepticism]" ''Zetetic Scholar'' (1987) No. 12/13, 3-4. "Though many in this category who dismiss and ridicule anomaly claims call themselves 'skeptics,' they often are really 'pseudo-skeptics' because they deny rather than doubt anomaly claims"</ref>
*Double standards in the application of criticism
*Double standards in the application of criticism <ref>Truzzi, ''ibid'', ".. they seem less inclined to take the same critical stance towards orthodox theories. For example, they may attack alternative methods in medicine (e.g., for a lack of double-blind studies) while ignoring that similar criticisms can be levelled against much conventional medicine"</ref>
*The making of judgments without full inquiry <ref>Truzzi, ''ibid'', "those I term scoffers often make judgments without full inquiry"</ref>
*The making of judgments without full inquiry
*Tendency to discredit, rather than investigate
*Tendency to discredit, rather than investigate <ref>Hyman, Ray, 1980. "Pathological Science: Towards a Proper Diagnosis and Remedy", ''Zetetic Scholar'', No. 6, 31-43. Truzzi wrote: ".. they may be more interested in discrediting an anomaly claim than in dispassionately investigating it"</ref>
*Use of ridicule or ''[[ad hominem]]'' attacks in lieu of arguments<ref>Truzzi, ''ibid'', "scoffers sometimes manage to discredit anomaly claims (e.g., through ridicule or ad hominem attacks) "</ref>
*Use of ridicule or ''[[ad hominem]]'' attacks in lieu of arguments
*Pejorative labeling of proponents as 'promoters', 'pseudoscientists' or practitioners of 'pathological science.'<ref>Truzzi, ''ibid'', "A characteristic of many scoffers is their pejorative characterization of proponents as "promoters" and sometimes even the most protoscientific anomaly claimants are labeled as 'pseudoscientists' or practitioners of 'pathological science.' "</ref>
*Pejorative labeling of proponents as 'promoters', 'pseudoscientists' or practitioners of 'pathological science.'
</td><td>
</td><td>
*Presenting insufficient evidence or proof <ref>Truzzi, ''ibid'', "scoffers sometimes manage to discredit anomaly claims .. without presenting any solid disproof</ref>
*Presenting insufficient evidence or proof
*Assuming criticism requires no burden of proof
*Assuming criticism requires no burden of proof <ref>Marcello Truzzi, "[http://www.anomalist.com/commentaries/pseudo.html On Pseudo-Skepticism]", ''Zetetic Scholar'', #12-13, 1987. "Critics who assert negative claims, but who mistakenly call themselves 'skeptics,' often act as though they have no burden of proof placed on them at all, though such a stance would be appropriate only for the agnostic or true skeptic"</ref>
*Making unsubstantiated counter-claims
*Making unsubstantiated counter-claims <ref>Truzzi, ''ibid'', ".. the true skeptic does not assert a claim, ''he has no burden to prove anything''. He just goes on using the established theories of 'conventional science' as usual. But if a critic asserts that there is evidence for disproof, that he has a ''negative hypothesis'' — saying, for instance, that a seeming psi result was actually due to an artifact — he is making a claim and therefore also has to bear a burden of proof."</ref>
*Counter-claims based on plausibility rather than empirical evidence <ref>Truzzi, ''ibid'', ".. many critics seem to feel it is only necessary to present a case for their counter-claims based upon plausibility rather than empirical evidence"</ref>
*Counter-claims based on plausibility rather than empirical evidence
*Suggesting that unconvincing evidence is grounds for dismissing it <ref>Truzzi, ''ibid'', "Showing evidence is unconvincing is not grounds for completely dismissing it."</ref>
*Suggesting that unconvincing evidence is grounds for dismissing it
<!--- This needs rewording since it is mostly directed at believers. *Tendency to dismiss ''all'' evidence <ref>Truzzi, ''ibid'', "Some proponents of anomaly claims, like some critics, seen unwilling to consider evidence in probabilistic terms, clinging to any slim loose end as though the critic must disprove all evidence ever put forward for a particular claim."</ref> -->
<!--- This needs rewording since it is mostly directed at believers. *Tendency to dismiss ''all'' evidence -->
</td></tr></table>
</td></tr></table>


== Pseudo-skepticism and scientific method ==
== Pseudo-skepticism and scientific method ==


Truzzi's argument begins with the premise that any phenomenon that has not been proven, does not imply that it has been disproven. But Truzzi went further, holding that any phenomena that had not been disproven, implies that it is plausible, and that anyone who does not consider both options equally, is pseudoskeptic. Truzzi wrote:<ref>"Marcello Truzzi, [http://www.anomalist.com/commentaries/pseudo.html On Pseudo-Skepticism]" ''Zetetic Scholar'' (1987) No. 12/13, 3-4.</ref>
Truzzi's argument begins with the premise that any phenomenon that has not been proven, does not imply that it has been disproven. But Truzzi went further, holding that any phenomena that had not been disproven, implies that it is plausible, and that anyone who does not consider both options equally, is pseudoskeptic. Truzzi wrote:<ref name="truzzi1"/>


{{quote|In science, the burden of proof falls upon the claimant; and the more extraordinary a claim, the heavier is the burden of proof demanded. The true skeptic takes an agnostic position, one that says the claim is ''not proved'' rather than ''disproved''. He asserts that the claimant has not borne the burden of proof and that science must continue to build its cognitive map of reality without incorporating the extraordinary claim as a new "fact." Since the true skeptic does not assert a claim, he has no burden to prove anything. He just goes on using the established theories of "conventional science" as usual. But if a critic asserts that there is evidence for disproof, that he has a negative hypothesis --saying, for instance, that a seeming psi result was actually due to an artifact -- he is making a claim and therefore also has to bear a burden of proof.
{{quote|In science, the burden of proof falls upon the claimant; and the more extraordinary a claim, the heavier is the burden of proof demanded. The true skeptic takes an agnostic position, one that says the claim is ''not proved'' rather than ''disproved''. He asserts that the claimant has not borne the burden of proof and that science must continue to build its cognitive map of reality without incorporating the extraordinary claim as a new "fact." Since the true skeptic does not assert a claim, he has no burden to prove anything. He just goes on using the established theories of "conventional science" as usual. But if a critic asserts that there is evidence for disproof, that he has a negative hypothesis --saying, for instance, that a seeming psi result was actually due to an artifact -- he is making a claim and therefore also has to bear a burden of proof.


Sometimes, such negative claims by critics are also quite extraordinary -- for example, that a UFO was actually a giant plasma, or that someone in a psi experiment was cued via an abnormal ability to hear a high pitch others with normal ears would fail to notice. In such cases the negative claimant also may have to bear a heavier burden of proof than might normally be expected."}}
Sometimes, such negative claims by critics are also quite extraordinary -- for example, that a UFO was actually a giant plasma, or that someone in a psi experiment was cued via an abnormal ability to hear a high pitch others with normal ears would fail to notice. In such cases the negative claimant also may have to bear a heavier burden of proof than might normally be expected.}}
It is common for fringe theorists and practioners to apply the label pseudoskeptic to anyone who is prepared neither to either investigate a claim or accept its conclusion. This is a misunderstanding of scientific method. Consider, for example, a test that is performed showing apparent evidence for [[Extrasensory perception|ESP]]. Based on experience of similar 'results', most scientists will suspect a flaw in the test. Scientific practice does not require every scientist to fully vet every experiment performed by every other scientist. Rather, scientific reports are reviewed by a number of peers, and where an experiment has produced interesting results, other scientists will try to reproduce it. If their results match, the evidence is accepted. If not, the original result is agreed to be an anomaly and it does not affect the acceptance of the dominant theory. To state that there must be a flaw in a test without relying on other tests would be pseudoskepticism; taking a position on the validity on the test does require accepting a [[Burden of proof (logical fallacy)|burden of proof]]. But simply choosing to ignore the test or declaring it to an anomalous result due to a contradiction to other tests is not pseudoskepticism, however frustrating it can be to those who welcome the apparent result of a test.
It is common for fringe theorists and practioners to apply the label pseudoskeptic to anyone who is prepared neither to either investigate a claim or accept its conclusion. This is a misunderstanding of scientific method. Consider, for example, a test that is performed showing apparent evidence for [[Extrasensory perception|ESP]]. Based on experience of similar 'results', most scientists will suspect a flaw in the test. Scientific practice does not require every scientist to fully vet every experiment performed by every other scientist. Rather, scientific reports are reviewed by a number of peers, and where an experiment has produced interesting results, other scientists will try to reproduce it. If their results match, the evidence is accepted. If not, the original result is agreed to be an anomaly and it does not affect the acceptance of the dominant theory. To state that there must be a flaw in a test without relying on other tests would be pseudoskepticism; taking a position on the validity on the test does require accepting a [[Burden of proof (logical fallacy)|burden of proof]]. But simply choosing to ignore the test or declaring it to an anomalous result due to a contradiction to other tests is not pseudoskepticism, however frustrating it can be to those who welcome the apparent result of a test.
Line 48: Line 49:
{{quote|[[appeal to authority|appeals to authority]], [[post hoc]] fallacies, ad hominem arguments and a whole host of other [[informal fallacy|informal errors]]. Nonetheless, because this inductive dimension of scholarship is often less implicitly presented for scrutiny, and because so much of the work of framing questions and establishing boundaries of scholarly discourse about 'the [[supernatural]]' were largely set anywhere from several generations ago … to a number of centuries ago ... the systematic bias of this tradition operates almost invisibly today.}}
{{quote|[[appeal to authority|appeals to authority]], [[post hoc]] fallacies, ad hominem arguments and a whole host of other [[informal fallacy|informal errors]]. Nonetheless, because this inductive dimension of scholarship is often less implicitly presented for scrutiny, and because so much of the work of framing questions and establishing boundaries of scholarly discourse about 'the [[supernatural]]' were largely set anywhere from several generations ago … to a number of centuries ago ... the systematic bias of this tradition operates almost invisibly today.}}


L. David Leiter, a member of the [[fringe science|fringe]] body [[Society for Scientific Exploration]], uses the terms 'pseudo-skepticism' and 'pathological skepticism' to refer to "organized skeptisicm", specifically the "Philadelphia Association for Critical Thinking" (PhACT)<ref>{{citejournal|title=The Pathology of Organized Skepticism |author=LD Leiter |journal= Journal of Scientific Exploration|date= 2002 |publisher= scientificexploration.org|url= http://www.scientificexploration.org/jse/articles/pdf/16.1_leiter.pdf}}</ref>, "[i]nstead of becoming scientifically minded, they become adherents of [[scientism]], the belief system in which science and only science has all the answers to everything" and that even many pseudoskeptics are unwilling to spend the time to "read significantly into the literature on the subjects about which they are most skeptical". He allows the following three states of mind: Leiter characterized people as either "continually and rigidly out of balance, in the direction of disbelief" (the ''pseudo-'' or ''organized skeptics''), "extremely gullible" or as having "rational balance." <ref>L. David Leiter, "[http://www.scientificexploration.org/jse/articles/pdf/16.1_leiter.pdf#search=%22%22Pathological%20skepticism%22%20pathology%22 The Pathology of Organized Skepticism]" (PDF), in ''Journal of Scientific Exploration'', Vol. 16, No. 1, pp. 125–128, 2002.</ref>
L. David Leiter, a member of the [[fringe science|fringe]] [[Society for Scientific Exploration]], uses the terms 'pseudo-skepticism' and 'pathological skepticism' to refer to "organized skeptisicm", specifically the "Philadelphia Association for Critical Thinking" (PhACT),<ref name="ldl">{{cite journal|title=The Pathology of Organized Skepticism |last=Leiter | first = L. David |journal= [[Journal of Scientific Exploration]]|date= 2002 |publisher= [[Society for Scientific Exploration]]|url= http://www.scientificexploration.org/jse/articles/pdf/16.1_leiter.pdf}}</ref> "[i]nstead of becoming scientifically minded, they become adherents of [[scientism]], the belief system in which science and only science has all the answers to everything" and that even many pseudoskeptics are unwilling to spend the time to "read significantly into the literature on the subjects about which they are most skeptical".


Prof. Hugo Meynell from Department of Religious Studies at the University of Calgary, labels as 'pseudo-skepticism' the "extreme position that all significant evidence supporting paranormal phenomena is a result of deception or lies".<ref>Michael Stoeber, Hugo Anthony Meynell, ''Critical Reflections on the Paranormal'', SUNY Press, 1996, ISBN 0791430634, 9780791430637 [http://books.google.co.uk/books?id=c_A_wfFe-CoC&pg=PA25&dq=Pseudo-skepticism&sig=ACfU3U372C-YJbYhNmNzNYVOmlVA78cnmQ#PPA16,M1 page 16]</ref> Psychiatrist Dr. Richard Kluft, MD has noted that:<ref>Kluft, Richard P., "Editorial: Building upon our foundations" (June 1994) in [http://scholarsbank.uoregon.edu:8080/dspace/handle/1794/1508 ''Dissociation'', Vol. 7, No. 2, p. 079-080], publ. Ridgeview Institute and the International Society for the Study of Dissociation</ref>
Prof. Hugo Meynell from Department of Religious Studies at the University of Calgary, labels as 'pseudo-skepticism' the "extreme position that all significant evidence supporting paranormal phenomena is a result of deception or lies".<ref>Michael Stoeber, Hugo Anthony Meynell, ''Critical Reflections on the Paranormal'', SUNY Press, 1996, ISBN 0791430634, 9780791430637 [http://books.google.co.uk/books?id=c_A_wfFe-CoC&pg=PA25&dq=Pseudo-skepticism&sig=ACfU3U372C-YJbYhNmNzNYVOmlVA78cnmQ#PPA16,M1 page 16]</ref> Psychiatrist Dr. Richard Kluft, MD has noted that:<ref>Kluft, Richard P., "Editorial: Building upon our foundations" (June 1994) in [http://scholarsbank.uoregon.edu:8080/dspace/handle/1794/1508 ''Dissociation'', Vol. 7, No. 2, p. 079-080], publ. Ridgeview Institute and the International Society for the Study of Dissociation</ref>

Revision as of 22:20, 10 October 2008

Marcello Truzzi founded the Zetetic Scholar journal, in which he popularised the term pseudoskepticism in the late 1980s

The term pseudoskepticism (or pseudoscepticism) denotes thinking that appears to be skeptical but is not. The term is most commonly encountered in the form popularised by Marcello Truzzi, where he defined pseudoskeptics as those who take "the negative rather than an agnostic position but still call themselves 'skeptics'".[1]

Truzzi's characterisation of pseudoskeptics

The term pseudoskepticism was popularised and characterised by Truzzi, in response to the skeptic groups who applied the label of "pseudoscientists" to fields which Truzzi preferred to describe as protoscience.[1]

While a Professor of Sociology at Eastern Michigan University in 1987, Truzzi gave the following description of pseudoskeptics in the journal Zetetic Scholar which he founded:

Over the years, I have decried the misuse of the term "skeptic" when used to refer to all critics of anomaly claims. Alas, the label has been thus misapplied by both proponents and critics of the paranormal. Sometimes users of the term have distinguished between so-called "soft" versus "hard" skeptics, and I in part revived the term "zetetic" because of the term's misuse. But I now think the problems created go beyond mere terminology and matters need to be set right. Since "skepticism" properly refers to doubt rather than denial--nonbelief rather than belief--critics who take the negative rather than an agnostic position but still call themselves "skeptics" are actually pseudo-skeptics and have, I believed, gained a false advantage by usurping that label."[1]

Truzzi attributed the following characteristics to pseudoskeptics:[1]

  • The tendency to deny, rather than doubt
  • Double standards in the application of criticism
  • The making of judgments without full inquiry
  • Tendency to discredit, rather than investigate
  • Use of ridicule or ad hominem attacks in lieu of arguments
  • Pejorative labeling of proponents as 'promoters', 'pseudoscientists' or practitioners of 'pathological science.'
  • Presenting insufficient evidence or proof
  • Assuming criticism requires no burden of proof
  • Making unsubstantiated counter-claims
  • Counter-claims based on plausibility rather than empirical evidence
  • Suggesting that unconvincing evidence is grounds for dismissing it

Pseudo-skepticism and scientific method

Truzzi's argument begins with the premise that any phenomenon that has not been proven, does not imply that it has been disproven. But Truzzi went further, holding that any phenomena that had not been disproven, implies that it is plausible, and that anyone who does not consider both options equally, is pseudoskeptic. Truzzi wrote:[1]

In science, the burden of proof falls upon the claimant; and the more extraordinary a claim, the heavier is the burden of proof demanded. The true skeptic takes an agnostic position, one that says the claim is not proved rather than disproved. He asserts that the claimant has not borne the burden of proof and that science must continue to build its cognitive map of reality without incorporating the extraordinary claim as a new "fact." Since the true skeptic does not assert a claim, he has no burden to prove anything. He just goes on using the established theories of "conventional science" as usual. But if a critic asserts that there is evidence for disproof, that he has a negative hypothesis --saying, for instance, that a seeming psi result was actually due to an artifact -- he is making a claim and therefore also has to bear a burden of proof. Sometimes, such negative claims by critics are also quite extraordinary -- for example, that a UFO was actually a giant plasma, or that someone in a psi experiment was cued via an abnormal ability to hear a high pitch others with normal ears would fail to notice. In such cases the negative claimant also may have to bear a heavier burden of proof than might normally be expected.

It is common for fringe theorists and practioners to apply the label pseudoskeptic to anyone who is prepared neither to either investigate a claim or accept its conclusion. This is a misunderstanding of scientific method. Consider, for example, a test that is performed showing apparent evidence for ESP. Based on experience of similar 'results', most scientists will suspect a flaw in the test. Scientific practice does not require every scientist to fully vet every experiment performed by every other scientist. Rather, scientific reports are reviewed by a number of peers, and where an experiment has produced interesting results, other scientists will try to reproduce it. If their results match, the evidence is accepted. If not, the original result is agreed to be an anomaly and it does not affect the acceptance of the dominant theory. To state that there must be a flaw in a test without relying on other tests would be pseudoskepticism; taking a position on the validity on the test does require accepting a burden of proof. But simply choosing to ignore the test or declaring it to an anomalous result due to a contradiction to other tests is not pseudoskepticism, however frustrating it can be to those who welcome the apparent result of a test.

Contemporary usage

A Spring 2006 course at the University of Colorado, "Edges of Science", promised to examine "the evidence for paranormal phenomena, [and] reasons for skepticism", including a section which shows "how a healthy skepticism can see through unsupported assertions, and how pathological skepticism can work against honest scientific inquiry."

Pennsylvania State University Folklorist David J. Hufford[2] uses the term "radical skepticism" to describe the unexamined prejudices and preconceptions which he argues are embraced by many — perhaps most — academic scientists. After reading and analysing the works of many skeptics and debunkers, Hufford argues that one can readily find:

appeals to authority, post hoc fallacies, ad hominem arguments and a whole host of other informal errors. Nonetheless, because this inductive dimension of scholarship is often less implicitly presented for scrutiny, and because so much of the work of framing questions and establishing boundaries of scholarly discourse about 'the supernatural' were largely set anywhere from several generations ago … to a number of centuries ago ... the systematic bias of this tradition operates almost invisibly today.

L. David Leiter, a member of the fringe Society for Scientific Exploration, uses the terms 'pseudo-skepticism' and 'pathological skepticism' to refer to "organized skeptisicm", specifically the "Philadelphia Association for Critical Thinking" (PhACT),[3] "[i]nstead of becoming scientifically minded, they become adherents of scientism, the belief system in which science and only science has all the answers to everything" and that even many pseudoskeptics are unwilling to spend the time to "read significantly into the literature on the subjects about which they are most skeptical".

Prof. Hugo Meynell from Department of Religious Studies at the University of Calgary, labels as 'pseudo-skepticism' the "extreme position that all significant evidence supporting paranormal phenomena is a result of deception or lies".[4] Psychiatrist Dr. Richard Kluft, MD has noted that:[5]

".. today genuine skepticism of the benign sort that looks evenly in all directions and encourages the advancement of knowledge seems vanishingly rare. Instead, we find a prevalence of pseudo-skepticism consist ing of harsh and invidious skepticism toward one's opponents' points of view and observations, and egregious self-congratulatory confirmatory bias toward one's own stances and findings misrepresented as the earnest and dispassionate pursuit of clinical, scholarly, and scientific truth."

Parapsychologist Susan Blackmore described the "worst kind of pseudoskepticism":[6]

"There are some members of the skeptics’ groups who clearly believe they know the right answer prior to inquiry. They appear not to be interested in weighing alternatives, investigating strange claims, or trying out psychic experiences or altered states for themselves (heaven forbid!), but only in promoting their own particular belief structure and cohesion . . . I have to say it—most of these people are men. Indeed, I have not met a single woman of this type."

Commenting on the labels "dogmatic" and "pathological" that the "Association for Skeptical Investigation"[7] puts on critics of paranormal investigations, Robert Todd Carroll of the Skeptic's Dictionary[8] argues that that association "is a group of pseudo-skeptical paranormal investigators and supporters who do not appreciate criticism of paranormal studies by truly genuine skeptics and critical thinkers. The only skepticism this group promotes is skepticism of critics and [their] criticisms of paranormal studies."[9]

Other usages

Prior to Truzzi, the term "pseudo-skepticism" had occasionally been used in 19th and early 20th century philosophy.

On 31 August 1869, Swiss philosopher Henri-Frédéric Amiel wrote in his diary:

My instinct is in harmony with the pessimism of Buddha and of Schopenhauer. It is a doubt which never leaves me, even in my moments of religious fervor. Nature is indeed for me a Maïa; and I look at her, as it were, with the eyes of an artist. My intelligence remains skeptical. What, then, do I believe in? I do not know. And what is it I hope for? It would be difficult to say. Folly! I believe in goodness, and I hope that good will prevail. Deep within this ironical and disappointed being of mine there is a child hidden — a frank, sad, simple creature, who believes in the ideal, in love, in holiness, and all heavenly superstitions. A whole millennium of idyls sleeps in my heart; I am a pseudo-skeptic, a pseudo-scoffer.[10]

In 1908 Henry Louis Mencken wrote on Friedrich Nietzsche's criticism of philosopher David Strauss that:

Strauss had been a preacher but had renounced the cloth and set up shop as a critic of Christianity. He had labored with good intentions, no doubt, but the net result of all his smug agnosticism was that his disciplines were as self-satisfied, bigoted, and prejudiced in the garb of agnostics as they had been before Christians. Nietzsche's eye saw this and in the first of his little pamphlets "David Strauss, der Bekenner und der Schriftsteller" ("David Strauss, the Confessor and the Writer"), he bore down on Strauss's bourgeoise pseudo-skepticism most savagely. This was 1873.[11]

Professor of Philosophy at the University of Illinois, Frederick L. Will used the term "pseudo-skepticism" in 1942. Alasdair MacIntyre writes:

[Frederick] Will was no exception. He began as an analytical philosopher, distinguishing different uses of language with the aim of showing that certain traditional philosophical problems need no longer trouble us, once we have understood how to make the relevant linguistic distinctions. The enemies were two: the philosophical skeptic who poses these false problems and the philosopher who thinks that the skeptic needs to be answered. So in "Is there a Problem of Induction?" (Journal of Philosophy, 1942) it is two senses of "know" that are to be distinguished: "All the uneasiness, the pseudo-skepticism and the pseudo-problem of induction, would never appear if it were possible to keep clear that 'know' in the statement that we do not know statements about the future is employed in a very special sense, not at all its ordinary one.[12]

Notre Dame Professor of English, John E. Sitter used the term in 1977 in a discussion of Alexander Pope: "Pope's intent, I believe, is to chasten the reader's skepticism — the pseudo-skepticism of the overly confident 'you' ... "[13]

Science writer C. Eugene Emery, Jr. compared the degrees of skepticism of CD-ROM-based encyclopedias of articles on pseudoscientific subjects. He called such articles "pseudoskeptical" if only suggested or stated that the subject was "controversial, but the author may not have a clue as to why".[14]

See also

Notes and references

  1. ^ a b c d e Truzzi, Marcello (1987). "On Pseudo-Skepticism". Zetetic Scholar (12/13): 3–4. Retrieved 2008-10-10.
  2. ^ "Reason, Rhetoric, and Religion: Academic Ideology versus Folk Belief", from New York Folklore, Vol. 11, Nos. 1-4, 1985 40th Anniversary Issue" quoted in part in Clark, Jerome, Unexplained! 347 Strange Sightings, Incredible Occurrences, and Puzzling Physical Phenomena; Detroit, Visible Ink Press; 1993, ISBN 0810394367; page 117
  3. ^ Leiter, L. David (2002). "The Pathology of Organized Skepticism" (PDF). Journal of Scientific Exploration. Society for Scientific Exploration.
  4. ^ Michael Stoeber, Hugo Anthony Meynell, Critical Reflections on the Paranormal, SUNY Press, 1996, ISBN 0791430634, 9780791430637 page 16
  5. ^ Kluft, Richard P., "Editorial: Building upon our foundations" (June 1994) in Dissociation, Vol. 7, No. 2, p. 079-080, publ. Ridgeview Institute and the International Society for the Study of Dissociation
  6. ^ JE Kennedy, "The Capricious, Actively Evasive, Unsustainable Nature of Psi: A Summary and Hypotheses", The Journal of Parapsychology, Volume 67, pp. 53–74, 2003. See Note 1 page 64 quoting Blackmore, S. J. (1994). Women skeptics. In L. Coly & R. White (Eds.), Women and parapsychology (pp. 234–236). New York: Parapsychology Foundation.
  7. ^ Association for Skeptical Investigation website
  8. ^ Skepdic article on positive pseudo-skeptics
  9. ^ Robert Todd Carroll "Internet Bunk: Skeptical Investigations." Skeptic's Dictionary
  10. ^ Charles Dudley Warner, Editor, Library Of The World's Best Literature Ancient And Modern, Vol. II, 1896. Online at Project Gutenberg (eg. here)
  11. ^ H. L. (Henry Louis) Mencken, The Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche (1908) publ. T.F. Unwin. Reprinted in Friedrich Nietzsche, Originally published: Boston : Luce and Co., 1913. p.30.
  12. ^ Alasdair MacIntyre "Foreword" to the book Pragmatism and Realism by Frederick L. Will (1997) quoting his earlier paper "Is There a Problem of Induction?" Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 39, No. 19 (September 10, 1942), pp. 505-513
  13. ^ John E. Sitter, "The Argument of Pope's Epistle to Cobham" Studies in English Literature, 1500-1900, Vol. 17, No. 3, Restoration and Eighteenth Century (Summer, 1977), pp. 435-449
  14. ^ C. Eugene Emery, Jr., "CD-ROM encyclopedias: how does their coverage of pseudoscience topics rate?", Skeptical Inquirer, Nov-Dec, 1996

External links

  • Skeptic's pages - Quotes and links to articles about skepticism and pseudoskepticism.